Introduction
This essay aims to illustrate the relevance of Leon Battista Alberti’s humanism to contemporary ecological challenges, particularly with regards to the relationship between humans, nature, and the arts, including architecture. In order to understand that relevance, Alberti’s work should be read as a holistic project lead by one all-compassing aim. The multiplicity of topics covered and the different literary styles give rise neither to obstacles to reading the works as a whole nor the suspicion of inconsistency. On the contrary, this variety is evidence of the breadth of his insight.
On the one hand, Alberti shows the power of the line, as the founding element for prospective constructions, along with other measurement tools, invented to describe reality, but mostly to design new inhabited spaces. His confidence in Nature, as a perfect model knowable through physical observation, is what opens up his new direction. For this reason, his works can be considered one of the first to draw a connection between the practical and theoretical spheres and a scientific concept of Art. Three treatises, De Pictura, Descriptio Urbis Romae, and De Statua will be the main references to support this argument.
On the other hand, in texts such as Vita S. Potiti, Della Familia, and Theogenius he investigates the inner attitude of living beings, made up of virtues but also faults, exploring its multiple connections on social structures, from the family through to the political, and their environment. He does not focus on practical transformations, but on human beings’ purpose that indirectly underlies and affects them. Both originate from the two interpretations of Nature. However, Alberti is able to find a convergence between these two apparently irreconcilable approaches. He strongly contributes to Arts and Architecture’s progress, without underestimating the destructive capacity of the human actions on Nature.
Nature as Machina Orbis
As mentioned above, before completing De Re Aedificatoria, Leon Battista Alberti had already explored how other art forms, such as painting and sculpture, could be reformed for a more secular and scientific culture. De Pictura, Descriptio Urbis Romae, and De Statua, represent the first field of investigation. Here, he combines theoretical and practical contributions, defining new artistic principles based on a specific idea of Nature, seen as visible and invisible structure, knowable through direct experience. This will be the basis for the future scientific method.
This different approach evidences, reading his claim, the importance of other disciplines in creating a stronger theoretical impact. He looks at both classical Greek and Latin authors and their legacy in mathematics and geometry, but also in poetry and rhetoric. However, more than any other discipline, Alberti considers geometry to be the foundation for painting, dedicating to it entirely De Pictura’s first chapter: “I want the painter, as far as he is able, to be learned in all the liberal arts, but I wish him above all to have a good knowledge of geometry” (L.B. Aberti, De Pictura, paragraph 53).
Later, in De Statua, geometry will be fundamental to understanding any natural body or environmental proportions, to be copied with the use of trilateration and coordinates. In fact, geometry, unlike the mathematical fields that deal with inner structures, is concerned with the physical appearance of the world as well.
As a result, in both treatises this discipline finds a practical application through new tools that open up knowledge of the environment as a tangible experience, that will affect new creative trajectories. The first treatise covers the invention of perspective. The visual rays, intersecting a surface, are the foundation of this new way of looking at the world. Those lines mediate the relationship between the human eye and the external world, describing it accurately. As a consequence, this descriptive process is used later to project pictures and buildings.
Whilst perspective still belongs to the abstract realm of drawing, in De Statua, Alberti invents new tools: normae, an object made by exempted and squares, used to record dimensions along the Cartesian coordinates, lengths, thickness and widths, and to describe “more stable and fix by Nature” (L.B. Alberti, De statua, paragraph 8); and the finitio, used to record curves and body variations like movements.
In spite of their differences, these tools allow the achievement of important new artistic principles: circumscription, composition, historia and reception of light. Within Descriptio Urbis Romae, he shows other similar tools, used on this occasion to describe a city: Rome. Through a numeric system of coordinates, a sort of parametrical precursor as suggested by Mario Carpo, he draws a series of connecting points and lines on the ground on which to create an accurate map: walls, gates, rivers, and monuments, all parts of an urban structure rather than sequences or single buildings. Alberti explains precisely how this process works:
Using mathematical instruments, I have recorded as carefully as I could the passage and the lineaments of the wall, the river, and the streets of the city of Rome, as well as the sites and locations of the temples, public works, gates, and commemorative monuments and the outlines of the hills, not to mention the area which is occupied by habitable buildings, all as we know them to be in our time. Furthermore, I have invented a method by which anyone, even a man endowed with only an average intellect, may make both exceptionally easily, and also very accurately, depictions on any surface, however large. It was some intellectuals, friends of mine, who moved me to do this, and I thought it good to assist their studies.
M. Carpo, Leon Battista Alberti’s Delineation of the city of Rome, 98
This accurate process leads to the definition of some principles that are similar to those for painting and sculpture, lineamenta, collocatio, and situs, crucial to planning and designing new parts of the city in the manner employed by Princes and Popes in Rome at the time, whereby they would extend lines to define intersections on the ground.
Lines, surfaces, and numbers, recorded by tools and defined by principles, would capture the Beauty “distributed by Nature” (L.B. Alberti, De statua, paragraph 12), providing it to humanity as a new cultural horizon.
However, the crucial thread in Alberti’s thought that encompasses all these processes and concepts is the idea of Nature as a perfect model to copy, and from which should come any principles and disciplines. Everything can be learned from Nature, conceiving it as a unique source, a perfect organism of shapes, movements, characters, and colors, and of the real Beauty. For this reason, over any other tools or principles, human eyes are the main medium through which to apprehend the external world. Together with the eyes, Alberti also mentions the role of the mind, which should select excellent examples “from the most beautiful bodies, and every effort should be to perceive, understand and express beauty” (L.B. Alberti, De Pictura, paragraph 55).
For the first time, Beauty is not an abstract idea, but a result of the selection of many beautiful examples. The artwork is the result of human invention and can be more perfect than Nature itself, even if it is a copy, opening up the debate on the transformation of Nature into artificial, and autonomous objects.
Although this idea of Nature is strongly reiterated in each of those three treatises, it is in De Pictura that Alberti begins a brief investigation of another meaning of Nature, as essence. This represents the immaterial side of living beings, the natural attitude, that, however always find an expression through the body, actions, purposes, etc.
Alberti explores this second interpretation in other works such as Apologhi, Della Famiglia, Theogenius, and Momus, but in this treaty, he relates it to the artistic world. De Re Aedificatoria is the only treatise that fully converges both aspects, thereby providing a specific role for the architect and the artist.
In chapter two, paragraph 41, Alberti explains how the painter should define a “historia”, a narrative of the painting, covering its general composition, its characters’ movements, and their bodily expressions:
A “historia” will move spectators when the men painted in the picture outwardly demonstrate their own feelings as clearly as possible. Nature provides that we mourn with the mourners, laugh with those who laugh, and grieve with the grief-stricken. Yet these feelings are known from movements of the body.
L.B. Alberti, De Pictura, paragraph 41
Claiming this, Alberti highlights the subtle thread that joins internal and external Nature, between human feelings and their bodies, community, and environment.
A few paragraphs later, in chapter three, Alberti adds that the painter’s aim as being to “obtain praise, favor and good-will for his work much more than riches. The painter will achieve this if his painting holds and charms the eyes and minds of spectators“. Later still, Alberti concludes that a good painter should be a good man, introducing a specific connection between his virtue, and his artistic work.
He is aware of the strong relationship between the artist, his outcomes, and his moral values. and at the end his spectators, that as a result, open up the civic issue of the role of art, which will become the crucial aim of architecture in creating a harmonious society.
Nature as Immanent Realm
A familiarity with some of Alberti’s previous dialogues, such as Apologhi, Della Famiglia, Theogenius, and Momus is essential to fully understand his idea of inner Nature (essence). These works are part of his ethical and social research, an attempt to give relief to the human soul and to probe human existential struggles1.
Each work is represented by one or more central characters: Saint Potitus in Vita S. Potiti, Batista and Giannozzo in Della Famiglia, Theogenius, Genipatro and Microtiro in Theogenius, Gelastus, and Enopus in Monus. Despite their differences, they are characterized by a similar style of narration2 that unveils the connection between the characters and their corresponding environments: wild nature for Saint Potitus; the city and the countryside for Batista, Theogenius, Genipatro, and Microtiro; and the underground world for Gelastus. These places are not just settings for each dialogue, but sophisticated and metaphorical mirrors to human behavior, their qualities, and their state of mind. In this sense, a “pre-ecological” thinking emerges here to describe a complex research trajectory that will find an answer in his theory of Architecture.
In Theogenius especially, Alberti employs a bucolic dialogue where this narrative form is used to assert that human beings, their nature, and their landscape can be conceived as a single entity, where external and internal realms are inextricably connected as a network, although they are visibly separated. Theogenius and Microtiro, the two main characters of this work, reflect on the idea of fortune and the valuable virtues of human beings whilst they are in the shade of the trees. This idyllic setting helps the reader to picture and consequently to understand their human qualities and the value of the philosophical topics they are exploring.
This harmonious intellectual atmosphere is disturbed by the entrance of Tichipedo, the owner of all the surrounding land, who brings with him the shadow of the urban landscape. As in many of the other dialogues, such as Della Famiglia, the bucolic landscape is seen as a model of Beauty and placed in contrast with the urban landscape, described as a place of ugliness marred by excessive and ostentatious wealth. On the one hand, pristine nature is the mirror of humanistic virtues and the real source of human fortune. On the other hand, the city is an image of the arrogance and malfeasance of human beings and the origin of their unstable and fragile fortunes.
In addition to offering a distinct concept of inner human nature and its effects on society, Alberti shows how it physically transforms the environment, opening up a further concern in how human beings conceive the transformative process, creative or not.
In the second part of Theogenius, Nature is described as having two aspects: its bucolic and magnificent elements and, in contrast, its dangerous manifestations. Alberti does not hide this latter aspect; he references many examples of urban catastrophes caused by floods, earthquakes, and volcanoes, recognizing the danger in many poisonous plants and savage animals. However, Alberti roundly condemns human beings, calling them “ominuccuoli”3 who, through their arrogance and restlessness, are the real cause of natural disasters. He is aware that the dangerous aspect of Nature is incomparable to the damage caused by humans.
It is a fact that Alberti’s judgment on human beings is cynical and clear-sighted: human beings too often demonstrate little consideration for their environment, including other similar living beings and animals. This means that, unlike in Barbaro’s approach, human actions could cause societal disruption and environmental damage if not guided by virtue and correct ethical behavior. This consciousness may have led Alberti to conceive of Nature as more than just a human resource, thus distancing himself from Cicero’s4 vision of human beings as explained in his De Natura Deorum5.
For the Latin writer, the human being is central to the whole of reality and has a more important role than other living things. Cicero’s use of particular terms demonstrates this belief: phrases such as “domitu nostro” and the “homine dominatus” clearly show how he frames nature from the human perspective. He gives legitimacy to the imposition of human will on plants by growing them and on animals by hunting or using them, guided only by human desires and only to their benefit. The human’s power is never denied and he is described as having a “domain”, which expresses an idea of absolute possession over natural resources. From Cicero’s point of view, the perfect and divine nature of the world is the basis of his claim to a specific hierarchy of living things. This perfection is not characterized by the idea of beauty; rather, its harmony is the result of divine wisdom and intellectual power. In consequence, humans receive a privileged place in comparison to others, giving them the full right to subjugate the world.
In contrast, Alberti’s vision of Nature can be aligned to some contemporary ecological thinking, where Nature is not a separate category from human beings but embraces all living beings equally. For this reason, the effects of the interaction between Nature and humans must be taken into consideration in all human activities.
Nature and Architecture as the Good Medicine
These arguments clearly support Eugenio Garin’s claim: Alberti considers Nature not just as a “Machina Orbis”, governed by numbers and a perfect and beautiful realm, but also in terms of its immanent side. This means considering the connection between inner and outer worlds, human and other living things, behaviors and environment, civic community, and urban structure, made up as a constellation of lines, mainly shaped by how human beings perceive culturally Nature, and the world outside.
The first interpretation of Nature contributes to building a new human creative horizon, rule-based and grounded in scientific and practical process. The second aims to frame the cultural issue that could lead humanity to a more peaceful and harmonious civic life. To achieve that, he carefully analyses many classical authors, such as Pliny, Ovid, Cicero, and Quintiliano, as well as hermetic philosophy6. These contributions are crucial when they suggest an ideal of Nature, as a boundless vital force, namely consisting of the inner ability to heal itself, like medicine. For instance, the “noble lie” 7 that involves the myth of Khora and its social use as Pharmakos, as argued by Plato in Timaeus and The Republic, could be the inspiration for Alberti’s aim to resurrect the Greek idea of the Polis, in which the urban structure and community are a unique body, due to the fundamental connection between citizens and their land. However, as further demonstrated below, Alberti does not embrace this connection, which meant the closure of the borders in the Polis. In the Seventh book of De Re Aedificatoria he claims: “Yet I don’t think that we ought to follow these who exclude strangers of every kind.” (L.B. Alberti, De Re Aedificatoria, Book 7, 191). This capacity to conceive of a united community does not preclude permeable borders and an idea of a territory for the many. On the contrary, this healing quality implies a consistent constituent aim that could be very fruitful. Changing the cultural approach on which human behavior is based could positively affect the social and physical environment.
In this sense, Architecture, through its civic role, could become the best discipline to address this change, as long as it is based on the principles identified above.
Momus can be considered a sort of bridge between these dialogues and the art treaties and the writing of De Re Aedificatoria, which could be seen as representing the culmination of his explorations.
In Momus, Alberti writes of a minor Greek god and his vicissitudes whilst in exile in the human world, and his travels between the heavens and earth following divine forgiveness. Although the story deals with a completely different subject to those described above, it can also be seen as a narrative device used by Alberti to highlight his disappointment with the current political powers in Rome, and showing the virtues and vices of human beings. Unlike his previous ethical works, the narrative is full of insights on architecture. It is a fact that during the same period, Alberti was writing De Re Aedificatoria, demonstrating the reason for these connections.
Focusing on some specific paragraphs makes Alberti’s idea of Nature and its relationship with the art world even clearer. Some confirm his claims from previous works, whilst others carry the idea yet further.
For instance, the first suggestion comes from the scene that takes place in the heavens. Here, all the other Gods are involved in a contest created by Jupiter’s request to add grace to the human world, giving it elegance and worth. Some gods invented different species of animal, Prometheus created human beings, Juno a house, etc. As a result, the human world receives these divine gifts but the beauty and pleasure they create immediately inspire envy in the same gods.
Encouraged by the others, Momus decides to provide his gift: insects and other disgusting animals. Here, Alberti confirms the Nature includes negative aspects as well, as already shown in Theogenius, but more than that he emphasizes again the virtues and vices of human beings.
However, what is very interesting is that the entire work is an investigation of human transformative actions: from Jupiter’s desire to disrupt the world that he himself designed, to the different places that Momus visits, the city and its public buildings, but also the pristine landscape, and even Charon’s realm, the Underworld. These places are crowded with all kinds of human beings, in all their variety and with different social behaviors. The misfortunes and fortunes of human beings are well described by Momus, who spends his exile on Earth discovering their different aspects. He goes to the city directly from the sky and here he tries many jobs to better understand how humans live. He encounters all kinds of characters, giving a description of a wide range of possible human behaviors. As in Theogenius, the city is the representation of human corruption, violence, and chaos, except for few places: the temple, that represents a civic and valuable place, where the god Virtue finds a refuge; and the countryside, where two philosophers, Socrates and Democritus, live excluded from the society. Again, the landscape is a mirror of society and, as in the Bucolic tradition, the countryside is a place of virtuous men rejected by a corrupt society.
In another scene, this dialectic opposition between pristine Nature and the city, between Nature and human transformations, reaches a crucial point. Following Gelasto and Charon’s journey from the Underworld to Earth, the reader is encouraged to reflect on the idea of Beauty, with both a harmonious visual dimension and a spiritual one, and the question of whether it belongs to the natural world or the artificial one.
Walking out of the Underworld towards the opposite side of Earth, Charon and Gelasto find themselves in a flowery field surrounded by a rural landscape. Charon is captivated by the smell and the views, which fill him with joy and astonishment. This idyllic scene is immediately brought to an end by Gelasto, who invites Charon to continue their journey in order to admire the human achievements in the city. Gelasto promises to find a place as wonderful as the flowery field: the theatre.
Through this scene, Alberti opens up a critical question: what is the relationship between Nature and Architecture? Is there a difference between the Beauty of Nature and the Architecture’s one? The answer is provided in the ensuing theatre scene and will be fully developed within De Re Aedificatoria.
Whilst walking towards the city, Charon asks Gelasto about the origin of this natural beauty. Gelasto offers him a philosophical explanation taken directly from Aristotle. Gelasto explains the Formal Cause, which is what gives matter its form, and the Final Cause, which gives a thing its purpose. Through the Formal and Final Cause, Nature reaches the most harmonious result, without contradiction.
Charon is unsatisfied with this explanation, which does not seem to capture the deep beauty of Nature, but rather confines it with theory. As they finally reach the theatre, Charon’s judgment is final:
You neglect the flower: should we admire the stone? Everything within the flower aims to beauty and grace. These human works are a waste of energy.
L.B. Alberti, Momus, 94
Nature’s beauty is unique and all-surpassing. However, Alberti enables the reader to discover a more nuanced view in the rest of the book. Two episodes involving Juno and Jupiter are particularly significant. In one episode, Juno asks Jupiter to further adorn her house with luxurious ornaments. This seemingly trivial event is, in fact, highly significant. This is where Alberti starts to divide good architecture from bad architecture, Aedificandi libido as defined by Alberto G. Cassani8. This is the opposite of civic architecture, which genuinely pursues the public good, as described within De Re Aedificatoria. In this sense, Architecture can reach an approximation of natural beauty, offering an optimistic perspective for human beings and their social structure.
In the second episode Jupiter, who represents political power and is a metaphor for Nicolo V, is shown as utterly obsessed with the idea of designing a new world that could strengthen his power over human beings. For this reason, he seeks advice from other gods and philosophers but realizes that architects would actually be of far more use to him. This final scene opens up the conviction that Architecture can be more valuable than philosophical thought in the ambition to build a different kind of society. The civic aim of Architecture is drawn. The continuity between De re Aedificatoria and Momus is now fully understandable, despite the different content.
Up to this point, Alberti’s writings have provided an idea of Nature, considering both aspects, more or less emphasised depending on the aim of various arguments of the treatises: external Nature, seen in its physical and theoretical model, and inner or immanent Nature as the essence of living beings. Both can lead to opposite cultural approaches and physical results since the interaction between these two produces human culture and artifacts, affecting the quality of a civic community.
In this sense, it is very meaningful the sentence included within the Preface of De re Aedificatoria:
Finally cutting of cliffs, the tunneling of mountains, the levelling of valleys, the containment of sea and lake waters, the emptying of swamps, the construction of ships, the rectification of course of rivers, the excavation of the outlets of waters, the constructions of bridges and ports, he not only resolved problems of temporary circumstance, but also opened the way toward every region of the earth. In this way people can exchange the partake of all that serves the improvement of health and way of life. (...)
L.B. Alberti, On the Art of Building in Ten Books, preface
Regarding this paragraph, Manfredo Tafuri, in Venice and Renaissance9, suggests a comparison between this paragraph and a similar statement by Daniele Barbaro10, to underline the subtle difference between them.
On the one hand, D. Barbaro similarly recognizes that universal harmony belongs to Nature for Arts. However, he also starts to consider it as a significant obstacle, asserting the importance of human actions over it. On the other hand, Alberti’s description of the human artifact’s impact on Nature shows the power used to modify ground into inhabited territories. Cutting cliffs is a very strong image in this sense, with their borders, inner shapes, their orography, and their geographical lines modeled directly by new machines and by an extraordinary transformative capacity. As explained above, this human activity should be not the cause of divisions and exploration, but rather of civil partnership, wealth, and prosperity, in consideration of Nature, not against it.
As a consequence, despite his concerns, Alberti provides here a cultural horizon where Architecture and the city can become the cure for society’s ills and the device to build a harmonious society, based on the same harmonious structure of Nature and its translation into a strong theoretical and practical approach and in-depth research.
However, to better understand how Alberti assigns architecture to the civic role, the Seventh, Eighth, and Ninth books of De Re Aedificatoria are essential. They are centered on the ornaments on the sacred buildings, both public and private. The Seventh book begins with this statement:
The principal ornament to any city lies in the siting, layout, composition, and arrangement of its road, squares, and individual works: each must be properly planned and distributes according to use, importance, and convenience. For without order there can be nothing commodious, graceful, or noble.
Here, Alberti asserts the importance that the urban structure is based on open spaces and public buildings, and a sort of hierarchy between them: function, importance, and convenience are the principles on which to build this organism and its community as a body or as a natural environment.
This approach can be considered usual and coherent with the character of the book.
However, recalling Alberti’s intellectual aim, this approach shows the correspondence between these artifacts and the urban essence, defined by characters, ornaments, shapes, materials, their locations, functions and in relation to their public or private role within the city. These elements and the symbolic location of the building represent here the relevance of the architectural relationships at any scale. The proper meaning and the use of Architecture and its Beauty depend on it.
It is in book Eight that, as suggested by Caspar Pearson in Humanism and the urban world: Leon Battista Alberti and the Renaissance city, Alberti develops further this topic. Its content is made up of a description of Alberti walking through the countryside toward the urban landscape. The movement itself is an interesting narrative strategy that emphasizes the structure of the urban space and focuses more on relationships than architectural objects. His journey starts from a view of the countryside, with its roads and houses, and the village is drawn following the natural shape of the terrain.
Alberti’s eyes are able to capture its beauty and harmony that arises not just from a system of numbers and proportion, but from the pleasantness of the landscape with the city seen in the distance.
Perhaps the decision to start his walk from here could be interpreted as a reference to Nature as the main model of Beauty and the primary architectural source. However, unlike in Theogenius and Momus, the conflictual dialectic between the countryside and the city is now dissolved. Through the movement of his walk, Alberti brings together those two landscapes without giving them any positive or negative attributes.
This absence is coherent with a description that attempts to contain few emotions or empathic thoughts. Alberti’s judgment is little affected by the environmental atmosphere or by an empirical experience. His ideas are formed through the rational process and are supported by his historical knowledge. This creates a text that is strongly characterized by objectivity and scientific reasoning, and which aims to highlight all the main principles that should characterize a harmonious civic space.
The description is interwoven with different textual content: historical references to validate Alberti’s statements; the classifications of all urban elements, e.g. roads, squares; accurate descriptions of mathematical proportions. The result is that the reader does not focus on the author and his movement through the city, but is able to concentrate on the principles described.
Alberti continues on his path, going through the graveyard, still outside the city, explaining their meanings, up to the city limits where he begins to analyze the role of the city gates and the different kinds of road. From this point on, the natural side of the city is left behind.
His entrance into the city is the chance to explain the importance to have three categories of roads: the ones with a specific character and shapes by reason of their uses and connections to their sacred places or public buildings, and those called common roads.
Moving through the description of theatres, amphitheaters, and places for the comitia, he suggests the right shapes, and the proper ornaments. These qualities, like the morphological ones, also have an important role within the urban body.
Moreover, he describes the importance of connecting public buildings with open spaces for pleasure, such as groves and pools. They give dignity to the city. The grove is shown in terms of its symbolic meaning. It represents the harmonious transformation of the territory and is a place where, close to other public buildings, everyday civic life takes place.
The same symbolic emphasis is given to the library. Placed in the center, this building replaces the medieval role of the church. It is the core of the new humanistic culture, where books are collected along with objects: mathematical instruments, maps and statues of ancient poets.
I shall only observe, that the principal ornament of a library, is the number and variety of the books contained in it, and chiefly their being collected from among the learned remains of antiquity. Another great ornament, are curios mathematical instrument of all sorts, especially if they are like that made by Posdonius, in which all the seven planets performed their proper revolution by their own motion.
L.B. Alberti, On the Art of Building in Ten Books, Book VIII, chapter 9, 183
The image of the mathematical instruments with the poets’ statues in the library represents the final image of a journey through Alberti’s thought. The Renaissance city should be governed by the convergence of rational thought and tools (such as those already found within De Statua), but also poetry and other valuable arts, in order to build a peaceful community.
The Ninth book, which is centered on the ornaments of private buildings, contains a full chapter dedicated to the principle of Concinnitas. Alberti strongly claims that any artistic process in Architecture should be based on Nature and this principle belonged to it:
Beauty is a form of sympathy ad consonance of the parts within a body, according to definite number, outlines and position, as dictated by Concinnitas, the absolute and fundamental rule in nature. This is the main object of art of building, and the source of her dignity, charm authority, and worth.
L.B. Alberti, On the Art of Building in Ten Books, Book IX, chapter 5, 303
In this particular sentence, Alberti shows a deep reverence for Nature as the origin of Beauty. He remarks on the difficulty in capturing this immaterial quality. The Concinnitas is described as the main principle, that produces a harmonic composition. This is not just an aesthetic quality, but also provides dignity, authority, and charm.
In this sense, Beauty does not represent just a final result of his theory of aesthetics. As explained at the begging of this essay, his theory does not exist without an ethical aim that should involve a single life and society.
Inheriting the Greek classical approach towards Nature, especially the one described within Timaeus, it is based on the geometrical figures and number. However, Nature is also the essence of life, the cause, a living organism. This establishes a deep connection between life and harmony: without harmony there is no life and no human beings and consequently Polis, looking at its physical and social aspects.
For this reason, Beauty, described as a result of Concinnitas, has the potential to represent the common feature of the two interpretations of Nature and their mutual forms of expression.
Looking at Architecture and Arts as the main origin of a harmonic world, Alberti is able to hold the classical approach—rediscovered introducing the idea of Gaia11—but to open it towards a Beauty that is the result of human transformation.
Conclusion
Looking at various contemporary philosophers and thinkers who deal with ecological issues, they agree that modernity has separated the natural realm from the cultural one, denying the ontological autonomy of those objects that are the products of this blending. This approach, perpetrating up to this century, has deeply affected most of the human contexts, political, economic, etc., characterized by little awareness and care about their effects on Nature and human beings themselves. In recent decades, thanks to ecological movements and many theoretical contributions such as those of Bruno Latour, it has been demonstrated that this separation has been misleading. For this reason, more than ever, Latour12 asserts an urgent need to define Nature in a different way, since many “natural” objects belong to this blending and no longer to one of the two worlds. All these insights arose from the international issues related to climate change and they seek to identify the ontological origin of this anthropocentric approach, in order to try to modify our cultural perspective. Although Alberti’s thought belongs to a different historical period, this does not mean that it is not a valid legacy from which we can still learn. In fact, Alberti’s idea of Nature that is not twofold or contradictory, as demonstrated above, appears to be an attempt to maintain the two categories Nature and Culture, looking for balance between human transformative action, which implies selection and separation of elements, and conservation. What Philippe Descola now suggests, namely moving beyond these categories, was part of Alberti’s investigations. This is evident from his works and his statements.
Moreover, by elevating Architecture and the city as the place of dignity and charm and underlining its civic role, Alberti assigns a key role to our discipline, proposing fundamental principles and new tools. If there are shortcomings in contemporary theory, these could be addressed through connections with one of the most transformative human actions: Architecture.
In this civic role architecture should provide a specific theoretical approach. Graham Harman recalls the concept of immateriality13, in order to bridge the modern misapprehension of separated realms. For him, Art and Architecture are crucial to demonstrate the new notion of Nature and drawing a new trajectory.
Manfredo Tafuri14 confirms this key role for Alberti, explaining that, from the Renaissance, the architectural object has been losing its autonomy and its immaterial side. For this reason, Leon Battista Alberti is deserving of greater in-depth research. His approach to the concept of Beauty and his related thinking would particularly repay further investigation into its relevance to addressing contemporary challenges and the new notion of Nature.